ABSTRACT. Background. Object omission is acceptable in English in specific contexts, as in (1), where the object of cleaning is omitted:
(1) John is cleaning the windows. He isn’t cleaning very well.
The phenomenon of object omission in English has long received considerable attention (e.g. Fillmore 1986; Martí 2015; Yankes 2021; Glass 2022), and recent accounts of object omission focus on different aspects of these contexts. For example, Rappaport Hovav & Levin (2024) and Folli & Harley (forthcoming) zoom in on a specific property of object omission: only animate entities can perform the action denoted by the verb in the absence of the object, as observed in (1) with the animate subject John. This predicts the marginal acceptability of (2), with an inanimate subject:
(2) The rain is cleaning the windows. ??It isn’t cleaning very well.
Accounts of the contrast — between contexts with (1) and without (2) an animate subject — place more focus on semantic or syntactic features of the context. Rappaport Hovav & Levin (2024) propose a polysemy-style account based on their analysis of the verb sweep: the lexicon contains both a ‘basic sweep’, which always requires an object, and a ‘conventionalised sweep’, which does not require an object but which requires that the subject be an Agent. In contrast, Folli & Harley (forthcoming) consider verbs of contact more generally and suggest that such contrasts may relate to a more pervasive distinction between animate and inanimate subjects, which may be reflected in multiple areas of syntax; more specifically, they propose that the cognitive primitive responsible for the observed distributions is that of goal-oriented action, a criterion which aligns with animacy to a considerable (if not complete) extent. In their analysis, object omission occurs through the coercion of verbs into a different predicate type with fewer arguments.
Despite the extent of this phenomenon, little quantitative research has been performed to establish the extent to which such factors play a role in object omission, or the extent of variation among verbs in their association with object omission. Moreover, the two accounts make different predictions: the approach of RH&L predicts a greater degree of lexical idiosyncrasy, while the syntactic account of F&H predicts greater transparency and uniformity, without excluding some degree of variation. This project tests these predictions to investigate the role played by animacy in object omission for English-speaking adults and children.
Method. The first phase of this study was an online experiment conducted with adults (N=80), who were native English speakers recruited on Prolific. Participants heard recordings of sentences such as (1) and (2) and rated their acceptability rating in a 7-point Likert format; sentences were presented individually, in randomized order, and had animate or inanimate subjects (within-subjects), with overt or omitted objects (between-subjects). In the second phase, these results were replicated using a written format instead of a spoken format, with the same number of participants and the same structure.
Results. We conducted a linear regression analysis with fixed effects of animate/inanimate and overt/omitted object and random effects for participant and verb, and z-scored ratings as the dependent measure. Both main effects were significant (ps < .001); importantly, so was the interaction (p<.001): with an inanimate subject, there were higher ratings with an overt object than with the object omitted; there was no difference with an animate subject. These results were replicated in the second phase. Thus, animacy and object presence are significant factors in predicting the acceptability of test sentences. However, variation was also identified among different verbs. For some verbs, object omission was significantly less acceptable with inanimate subjects (e.g. wash); for other verbs, object omission was acceptable with both animate and inanimate subjects (e.g. cook). Surprisingly, for some verbs (e.g. sweep), sentences with inanimate subjects were rated significantly lower than sentences with animate subjects, even with overt objects. Some minor variations were also encountered between phases; for example, sentences involving cook with inanimate subjects and object drop had ratings that were significantly lower than the overt object versions (although still above the median) in the written study, but not in the spoken study.
Next Steps. These studies will also be situated within the context of the broader research programme of which they form part. In the third phase of this programme, differences will be examined between animate subjects acting intentionally and animate subjects whose actions are not under their control and hence not goal-oriented (cf. Martin et al. forthcoming). Preliminary results from this phase will also form part of the presentation. In the fourth phase, the interaction of animacy and object drop in young children (24–28 mos) is investigated using the Central Fixation Paradigm (Shi et al 2006). Our ultimate analysis of the syntactic basis of this phenomenon will incorporate data from all these phases of research.
The irregular complementation of prepositions in English: The case of far from
ABSTRACT. Although prepositions typically take nominal complements, reference grammar of English has described a range of irregular complements, as in from behind the curtain (prepositional complement), until recently (adverbial complement), agree on whether we should call in the police (interrogative clause), and for dead (adjectival complement) (Huddleston and Pullum 2002: 599). These complements are considered less typical, since they show highly selectional (or collocational) restrictions compared to nominal complements (ibid.: 599). However, non-nominal complements are not necessarily untypical in some cases.
This study investigates the complements of far from. The phrase far from is pervasive in Present-day English and takes various irregular complements, as shown below:
(1) (a) But, in my opinion, oil painting is far from perfect.
(b) His eyes suddenly flash. “You are far from boring, Barnaby,” he says, …
(c) historians are still far from agreed on the precise answers to these questions, …
(d) But she far from destroyed the material, …
(e) … he hadn't been the only one. Far from it.
The complements of far from are adjectival in (1a), present participial in (1b), past participial in (1c), and verbal in (1d), serving a negating function similar to not. In (1e), far from it makes up an independent phrase meaning ‘certainly not.’
Previous scholarship, such as Brinton and Inoue (2020) and De Smet, Norde, Van Goethem, and Vanderbauwhede (2015), have partially captured the diachronic and typological functions of far from. They mainly focused on its functions as a downtoner and pragmatic marker. However, the distribution and frequency of its irregular complements—particularly verbal complements—have received little attention.
To address this gap, the present study conducts two corpus-based investigations. The first examines the types of complements taken by far from in Present-day British English analyzing 1) complement types of far from, and 2) phrasal types of far from across four corpora; Lancaster1931, LOB, FLOB, and BE21, each being composed of one million British English from 1931, 1961, 1991 and 2021, respectively. These corpora were compiled with consistent register and time-span criteria. Key findings include 1) 215 occurrences of far from across the four corpora, 2) the continued prevalence of irregular complements, including 70 present participial forms, 43 adjectival complements, 10 past participial forms and others (See the table in the pdf file), 3) 10 occurrences of the independent use of Far from it, 4) the frequent use of far from as the head of dependent phrases, and 5) 41 hits of far from following another negative element such as not or never.
The second study analyzes a new use of far from that appears to take a verbal complement, using the NOW corpus, which contains 21.6 billion words (as of 19/04/2025). It investigates instances of far from followed by a present-tense verb, since past forms and past participial forms are often identical. The findings include: (1) the types and tokens of far from + present-tense verb is very limited compared to other irregular complements, and 2) perception and thinking verbs, such as confirm, solve, prove and reflect, tend to occur in this construction.
This study makes two contributions: first, it investigates the distribution of irregular complements of far from across four British English corpora with consistent register and time-span criteria; and, second, it explores the token and type frequency of verbal complements, an area that has received little attention in previous scholarship.
References
Brinton, Laurel J. and Tohru Inoue (2020) “A far from simple matter revisited: The ongoing grammaticalization of far from,” 271-294. In Merja Kytö and Erik Smitterberg (eds). Late Modern English Novel encounters. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Huddleston, Rodney & Geoffrey K. Pullum (2002) The Cambridge grammar of the English language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
De Smet, Hendrik, Muriel Norde, Kristel Van Goethem, and Gudrun Vanderbauwhede (2015) “Degrees of adverbialization: A cross-linguistic corpus-study of ‘far from X’ constructions.” (available at https://www.scribd.com/document/738918339/De-Smet-et-al-2015-Degrees-of-adverbialization)
Corpora
The BE21 Corpus / The FLOB Corpus / The NOW Corpus / The Lancaster 1931 Corpus / The LOB Corpus
Decomposing sentence-final particle ma in Mandarin
ABSTRACT. This paper investigates the syntactic structure of the Mandarin sentence-final particle ma, traditionally viewed as a clause-typing yes-no question marker, and its relation to the attitude particle a. Challenging the standard view that ma independently occupies a peripheral projection, the authors propose a decompositional analysis, in which ma is not a functional head but a complex structure derived through head movement. Specifically, ma originates as a Polarity (Pol) head above TP, undergoes successive head movement through an interrogative Force head, and ultimately lands an Attitude projection (AttP), explaining its sentence-final surface position and its incompatibility with the independent particle a. The proposed structure accounts for ma’s inability to co-occur with a, while allowing a to combine with other polar markers like mei or a null ∅ marker. Empirical data from scope ambiguity, embedded questions, and speaker expectation contexts support this syntactic decomposition. The paper’s analysis sheds light on the nature of polarity encoding, clause-typing, and the interaction between syntactic structure and speaker attitudes in Mandarin interrogatives.
ABSTRACT. There have been two main syntactic approaches to the sentence-final particle "ma" in Mandarin: some argued that it is a Disjunction Phrase (DisjP) equivalent to English or not (e.g. Tang 2015), while others argued that it is a head in the left periphery such as C0 or (illocutionary) Force0 (e.g. Pan 2022). This paper supports the latter approach by contrasting "ma" with two SFPs "fe" and "me" in Yixing Chinese, a variety of Wu Chinese spoken in China’s Jiangsu province. We argue that in contrast to "ma", Yixing "fe" and "me" are largely equivalent to English "or not".
Then we compare Mandarin and Yixing with English. Following Hamblin (1973), Biezma (2015) and others, there are two strategies to formulate a polar question: one using a polar DisjP (e.g. "I wonder whether or not John drinks coffee in English"), and the other without any DisjP (e.g. "I wonder whether John drinks coffee in English"). We argue that English has both strategies, while Mandarin "ma"-questions have no DisjP, and Yixing "fe"/“me”-questions always involve a DisjP.
On-ta-logy: An Analysis of the Non-referential Use of ta in Mandarin Chinese
ABSTRACT. This paper investigates a form-meaning mismatch in Mandarin Chinese involving 'ta', traditionally known as the third-person singular pronoun. We examine cases where 'ta' appears non-referentially where it signals excessive quantity rather than referring to any entity.
Through careful examination of distributional patterns and interaction with other focus particles, we demonstrate that 'ta' functions as a scalar focus-sensitive particle, requiring its associate to occupy a high position on a contextually determined scale. This analysis overcomes limitations of previous accounts that treated 'ta' as either a second object or an expletive pronoun, which respectively predicted unattested tritransitive verbs or violated Mandarin's pro-drop nature.
Based on constituency tests and scope relationships, we argue that the verb moves across 'ta', allowing proper c-command relations - a pattern also observed with focus particles in Italian. Diachronic evidence reveals that this usage evolved from the common swearing phrase 'ta-ma-de' ('fucking' or 'damn'), explaining the shared form with the pronoun while maintaining distinct syntactic and semantic properties.
Textsetting problems between metrical and musical constraints: The treatment of vowel clusters in sixteenth-century Italian madrigals
ABSTRACT. This talk addresses a central issue in the musical textsetting of Italian metrical texts: the treatment of vowel clusters which should be metrically rendered as tautosyllabic (Avalle, 1982; Menichetti, 1993; Lannutti, 1994). Focussing on the 16th-century Italian madrigal repertoire, I will first demonstrate how ensuring that these vocalic clusters are perceived as tautosyllabic in a musical setting places severe constraints on the available melodic and contrapuntal options. I then examine how composers address this issue, and the trade-offs involved in their choices. Finally, the polygenetic nature of this problem will be demonstrated by drawing comparisons with examples from other musical traditions, including 18th-century Italian opera and 20th-century popular music.
ABSTRACT. Traditionally, Italian is analysed with bimoraic trochees (Bafile, 1999). Conversely, the stable presence of iambs in the language constitutes strong counter evidence. This paper demonstrates a systematic interaction between hierarchical musical structure and prosodic organisation in the text-tune composite (following Dell & Halle, 2009). In particular, rightheaded time-spans, identified through reductional analysis (GTTM; Lerdahl & Jackendoff, 1983), consistently align with iambic metrical patterns in the linguistic domain. Data indicate that, alongside the expected trochees, marked iambs can be recognised and recruited under conditions of enhanced salience, such as when guided by musical prominence. This points to a more flexible and dynamic model of Italian prosody where both trochaic and iambic feet coexist (as already seen in Marotta 1999, 2012).
Headless ternary feet. A case of catalexis on the left in Italian pop songs.
ABSTRACT. Musical triplets are left-headed ternary rhythmic elements. They create phenomenal
accents (Lerdahl & Jackendoff, 1983) with the onset of the triplet being metrically stronger than the following two notes. When ternary linguistic strings are sung in triplets, data from my corpus of Italian songs show a preference for text-to-tune alignment (Proto & Dell, 2013), both word-internally and across word boundaries. Moreover, headless triplets (i.e. triplets whose onset aligns with a rest) show preference of alignment with headless ternary feet. The head of these feet is visible to the algorithm – governing only weak syllables – but segmentally empty, a particular case of catalexis on the left. This aligns with the notion of ‘loud’ silence found in music literature (e.g., London, 1993).
Irish English in theatre and natural speech: The productive use of salient features in playscripts for grammatical investigations [Themed Session: Literary Linguistics]
ABSTRACT. Literature, including dramas and playscripts, provides good material for examining the actual language in use. This paper discusses a methodology for using playscripts for linguistic studies, by introducing my research data on morphosyntax of Irish English in literature and in natural speech. The paper focuses on playscripts by John B. Keane (1928-2002), a playwright and publican known for writing in the local language of County Kerry, southwest Ireland. His plays exhibit various lexical and grammatical features that Dolan (1999) collects and Filppula (1999) describes for Irish variations of English, known as Hiberno-English.
The following passages are cited from "Sive" (1959). The three morphosyntactic features are scrutinised in the paper: "do be" habitual, "be after" perfect, and the "’tis…" construction.
(1) I know! I know! The money is a great temptation but there is wrong in it from head to heel. Sive is young, with a brain by her. She will be dreaming about love with a young man. ’Tis the way young girls do be!
(2) We’re only just after rising from the table. ’Twould be a waste.
(3) Will you listen to him cnabshealing again? He’s never happy unless ’tis grumbling he is. Wouldn’t you have the good word, anyway? […] ’Tisn’t going around stealing the dead out of their graves we are.
The paper accesses how these morohosyntactic features in playscripts reflect actual language in use in past and present and suggests ways in which literary works can be used to elucidate grammar. This is undertaken with reference to corpora and my fieldwork data, including elicitation sessions with native speakers of Southwest Irish English.
While speech in plays and dramas are often criticised as “stage fake” in terms of language ideologies (for this, one could think of John M. Synge (1871-1909)), my study insists that the use of language in playscripts is underpinned by linguistic intuition of the local writer and thus reveals the reality of language. The do be form, the be after form, and the ’tis… construction reveal certain distributions in grammar, outlining rules in the system of Irish English. These forms and constructions are also distributed in speakers’ awareness of “Irishness” and “Standard” (Shimada 2016). The paper notes the importance of inclusion in description not only of speakers’ knowledge of language but also of sociolinguistic awareness. The productive use of literature for linguistic research is emphasised.
References: Dolan, Terence Patrick (1999) A dictionary of Hiberno-English: The use of Hiberno-English. Gill and Macmillan. / Filppula, Markku (1999) The grammar of Irish English: Language in Hibernian style. London: Routledge. / Shimada, Tamami (2016) Speakers’ awareness and the use of do be vs. be after in Hiberno-English. World Englishes 35, 310-323.
An investigation of Irish accent representation in Rudyard Kipling’s “Three Musketeers” stories General Session
ABSTRACT. Thesis
This paper presents a corpus-informed dialectal examination of Rudyard Kipling’s series of short stories featuring three soldiers stationed in India during the British Raj, known as the “Three Musketeers”. Each speaker’s contribution is written with orthographic alterations indicating differing dialects - Ortheris, a Cockney; Learoyd, a Yorkshireman; Mulvaney, an Irishman. Raine (1992, p12) argued that “dialect is Kipling’s greatest contribution to modern literature … and he is the most accomplished practitioner since Burns.” To our knowledge, however, there has been no systematic attempt to describe the Irish dialect found in Kipling’s Three Musketeers stories.
Methodology
Using a corpus of the stories to investigate Kipling’s dialect writing, we focus on the direct speech of Mulvaney. Well-known techniques and difficulties in expressing any dialect in writing will be initially discussed, particularly in the absence of a prescribed standard for Irish/ Hiberno English (Connell 2014 p39) and the need to maintain “the precarious balance of mimetic commitment and communicative exigency” (Sternberg 1982, p114 in Toolan 1992, p31). This exploration of literary dialect techniques will also highlight the value of the mixed method approach adopted for this investigation which incorporated micro-close readings of the stories in order to ascertain patterns of feature use both within and across stories, as well as macro, computational driven techniques for feature searching.
Following this, relevant and more notable phonological features of Irish/Hiberno English will be reviewed (Kallen 1994; Hickey 2004), including DRESS to KIT (e.g. ‘whin’ for when), and orthographic ‘th’ to ‘d’ (e.g. ‘wid’ for with), and we will discuss how these are represented across the stories in the corpus.
Emerging Results
Initial results suggest varying degrees of consistency. The adoption of ‘wid’ for with is fairly consistently applied and uniform. However, the situation regarding DRESS to KIT appears more complex. Indeed, some forms are invariable across the corpus with respect to the use of ‘i’ (e.g. ‘rig’mint’ for regiment), while others consistently use ‘e’ (e.g. ‘end’ and its derived forms ‘ended’ and ‘ending’), despite there being no potential ambiguity or lexical mergers between ‘end’ and ‘ind’. Thus, we explore the effects of ambiguity on orthographical changes in relation to syntactic processing as a means of exploring possible motivations for Kipling not altering the representative vowel in, for example, ’red’ (to ‘rid’), but consistently altering the form of ‘then’ to ‘thin’.
An Alternative to Suppression: How Mainstream Media Diverts Narratives through Agenda-Setting and Framing
ABSTRACT. To be considered for Poster Presentation-Subject: Literary Linguistics
This paper examines mainstream media's role in shaping public discourse through strategic agenda-setting and framing practices, focusing on the high-profile December 2024 shooting of UnitedHealthcare CEO Brian Thompson by Luigi Mangione. Utilizing Chomsky and Herman’s Propaganda Model (Herman & Chomsky, 1989) alongside McCombs and Shaw’s theories of first- and second-level agenda-setting (McCombs & Shaw, 1972), as well as Entman’s conceptualization of framing (Entman, 1993), this study investigates how media narratives around the event selectively highlighted certain aspects while marginalizing critical systemic perspectives.
Drawing on qualitative analysis of diverse media sources—including newspapers, online platforms, and social media content—the research illustrates how initial portrayals emphasizing Mangione's alleged ideological motivations and symbolic protest quickly shifted towards personalized narratives of pathology, criminality, and sensationalism. By systematically examining linguistic framing choices and narrative structures adopted by mainstream outlets, the analysis demonstrates that the analyzed media in question deliberate diverts reader’s attentions away from deeper structural issues in the United States of America, with the prime example of this being in the healthcare system
A comparative analysis further contrasts the media portrayal of Mangione’s case with coverage of the 2023 killing of Jordan Neely, highlighting stark differences based on victim and perpetrator social identities. This contrast reveals broader patterns of selective narrative visibility, issue salience, and ideological bias inherent in mainstream media representations.
Ultimately, the paper argues that contemporary media power operates not primarily through outright suppression, but rather through sophisticated diversion and reframing strategies that subtly reinforce dominant ideological structures and deflect meaningful discussions on structural inequities.
References:
Entman, R. M. (1993). Framing: Toward clarification of a fractured paradigm. Journal of Communication, 43(4), 51–58. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1460-2466.1993.tb01304.x
Herman, E. S., & Chomsky, N. (1989). Manufacturing consent: The political economy of the mass media. Pantheon Books.
McCombs, M. E., & Shaw, D. L. (1972). The agenda-setting function of mass media. Public Opinion Quarterly, 36(2), 176–187. https://doi.org/10.1086/267990
ABSTRACT. Ditransitive Constructions in Baritle Neo-Aramaic (General Session)
This study investigates the structure of ditransitive constructions in Baritle, a North-Eastern Neo-Aramaic language of Iraq, drawing on newly collected data obtained through fieldwork and native-speaker intuition. It addresses the following research questions: (1) What are the different constructions of ditransitive verbs in Baritle? and (2) What factors determine these constructions?
Baritle uses the dative marker da, ‘to, for’, with ditransitive verbs to mark nominal indirect objects. (Nominal indirect object is in bold)
(1) Ditransitive verb with nominal indirect object
ʔaxni k-mdaṛb-ax ʔa:ða kθa:wa da ˈMatte.
IPL IND-send.IPFV-1PL.SU this.M book.M DAT Matte(M.name)
‘We send this book to Matte.’
However, Baritle uses the dative marker ɣdal-, ‘to/for’, with independent pronominal indirect objects. (Independent pronominal indirect object is in bold)
(2) Ditransitive verb with independent pronominal indirect object
ʔaxni k-mdaṛb-ax-le ˈɣdal-eh. .
IPL IND-send.IPFV-1PL.SU-3SG.M.OBJ DA-3SG.M
‘We send it to him.’
Similar to other Semitic languages, Baritle’s verbal morphology encompasses both non-concatenative (root-and-pattern) and concatenative (affixal) elements, with the former being referred to as verb bases. For instance, the triliteral root q-ṭ-l, ‘to kill’, is used as qa:ṭəl- in the imperfective aspect and qṭəl- in the perfective aspect. All subjects and objects that appear in the presupposition—a linguistic concept associated with information already assumed to be known by the hearer (Lambrecht 1994: 52)—obligatorily trigger agreement in the verbal complex (Al-Saka 2021). For example, the imperfective verb base can carry up to two agreement morphemes. Thus, in a simple intransitive or transitive imperfective, both arguments may be cross-referenced as suffixes directly on the verb. The first agreement morpheme marks subject agreement, while the second marks object agreement (Agreement is in bold below).
(3)
a. Intransitive verb
ʔaxni k-qa:ɻ-ax ˈħe:le.
IPL IND-read.IPFV-1PL.SU a lot
‘We read a lot.’
b. Transitive verb, object in narrow focus (definite/indefinite)
ʔaxni k-ṣoʔ-ax ɣða ˈbəlla / ˈbəllətt-an.
IPL IND-paint.IPFV-1PL.SU one.F door(F.) door(F.)-1PL.POSS
‘We paint A DOOR/OUR DOOR.’
c. Transitive verb, verb focus, presupposed object
ʔaxni ˈk-ṣoʔ-ax-la bəlla.
IPL IND-paint.IPFV-1PL.SU-3SG.F.OBJ door(F.)
‘We PAINT the door.’
In Baritle, the progressive aspect may be formed by adding the enclitic auxiliary -ʔi-, ‘be’, onto an imperfective base, introducing an additional agreement slot on the auxiliary itself. The auxiliary has two phonologically conditioned allomorphs: yy and ii. In (4), there is an agreeing object and the agreement morpheme that appears on the auxiliary represents a second instance of agreement with the subject. (Subject agreement is in bold, object agreement is in bold italics)
(4) Progressive Transitive, verb focus, presupposed object
ʔaxni ˈk-ṣoʔ-ax-la=yy-ax bəlla.
IPL IND-paint.IPFV-1PL.SU-3SG.F.OBJ=be-1PL.SU door(F.)
‘We are PAINTING the door.’
The double subject agreement is limited to the first and second persons, so the third person double subject agreement is blocked in Baritle.
Ditransitive verbs with two agreeing objects (i.e., two presupposed or pronominal objects) exhibit a surprising pattern. First, these ditransitive verbs employ the enclitic auxiliary, making the ditransitive verbal complex look like the progressive verbal complex. Second, the auxiliary
agrees with the direct object. (Object agreement is in bold)
(5) Ditransitive, verb focus, presupposed objects
ʔaxni ˈk-mdaṛb-ax-lux=i-le.
IPL IND-send.IPFV-1PL.SU-2SG.M.INDOBJ=AUX-3SG.M.OBJ
‘We SEND you(m.) it(m.).’
However, the first- and second-person direct object suffixes cannot be combined with an indirect object suffix on a verb complex. When a verb has a first- or second-person direct object suffix, the indirect pronominal object must be expressed as a suffix on the preposition ɣdal- ‘to’, which is placed as an independent phrase. This restriction reflects a fixed hierarchy in the ordering of suffixes on a verb (Corbett 2006). (Object agreement and the prepositional phrase are in bold)
(6)
a. First person pronominal direct object
ʔa:yən ˈk-mdaṛb-a:-li ɣdal-en.
3SG.F IND-send.IPFV-3SG.F.SU-1SG.OBJ DAT-3PL
‘She SENDS me to them (to help them).’
b. Second person pronominal direct object
ʔa:yən ˈk-mdaṛb-a:-lux ɣdal-en.
3SG.F IND-send.IPFV-3SG.F.SU-2SG.M.OBJ DAT-3PL
‘She SENDS you to them’
In summary, ditransitive constructions in Baritle have different structures based on the type of the indirect object (nominal or pronominal) and the person of the object.
References
Al-Saka, Vean. 2021. ‘Verbal Syntax and Differential Object Marking in Baritle Neo-
Aramaic’. Unpublished PhD dissertation, Newcastle University
Corbett, Greville. 2006. Agreement. Cambridge. Cambridge University Press.
Lambrecht, K. 1994. Information Structure and Sentence Form: Topics, Focus, and the Mental
Representations of Discourse Referents. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Syntax of Complex Wh-phrases in The Left Periphery in Bani Malik Asiri Arabic
ABSTRACT. Bani Malik Asiri (BMA) exhibits complex wh-phrases in the left periphery of wh-interrogatives known as pied piping (Ross, 1967). In BMA, the possessive structure is one of the constructions targeted by this phenomenon. Following Cable (2007), I argue that the existence of complex wh-phrases in the left edge of interrogative clauses is not a real pied-piping as it takes place as a secondary consequence of an overt movement of a QP headed by a null Q-particle and has a possessive wh-phrase as a complement as in (1.a,b) below. (1) a. gara xalid ∅ ktab man . read Khalid Q book whose . ‘Whose book did Khalid read?’ b. ∅ ktab man gara xalid ti . Q book whose read Khalid . . ‘Whose book did Khalid read?’ The complexity of wh-phrases in BMA can be more complicated as illustrated in (2). (2) ∅ manj ktab-ahj gara xalid . Q who book-his read Khalid . ‘Who his book did Khalid read?’ This type of construction is known as resumptive possessor-extraction. Cable (2007) argues that the resumptive pronoun is the true possessive specifier of the clause-internal DP and the QP is adjoined to the resumptive pronoun. However, I propose a different analysis that works for BMA data. I argue that the QP is base-generated in spec-CP. Given this, I follow the spilt-CP hypothesis by Rizzi (1997, 2001b, 2004), I assume that the CP in (2) is complex and has two distinct probes: (i) Force that has an [uQ] feature; and has a QP merged directly in its specifier to satisfy this feature, and (ii) Foc that has a [+Foc] feature and triggers ktab-ah to move to the spec-FocP.
ABSTRACT. Based on a pitch analysis of 500 Zulu phrases, this study measured that nearly all major pitch shifts within Zulu tonal domains occur in approximate harmonic intervals of 4, 7, and 12 semitones. Additionally, the boundary pitch of a tonal segment may harmonise with multiple domain positions, and a domain may contain layers of harmonic relations (e.g., [[waː] [ɬaka[n[iː]]]pha], where brackets indicate harmonic intervals).
These findings challenge the view in Ladd (2008) that speech pitch lacks the consistency of musical intervals and also raise questions on Patel’s (2008) description that each tone “is used where it is linguistically appropriate” and lacks the organisation feature of musical intervals. Finally, the aim of this paper is to utilise the interval analysis to examine the interaction patterns among Zulu depressor phonetics, lexical tonal phonology and intonational morphology.
ABSTRACT. This talk examines commonalities between reversing operations found in language games and pitch patterns found across musical genres. Linguistic studies of language games (e.g., Bagemihl, 1995) provide evidence for hierarchical constituency in phonological representations. Equivalent hierarchical representations are also used in studies of similarities between grouping structures in music and language (e.g. Fabb & Halle, 2011). Argentino & Mackenzie (2019) analyse serial music using formalisms developed in phonological studies of language games, arguing that these offer a simpler account of serial transformations compared to traditional serial operations. This talk extends this proposal by applying language game formalisms to the study of jazz and post-tonal repertoire.
Developmental trajectories of music and language acquisition
ABSTRACT. Music and language are intertwined in many aspects and their processing requires
overlapping neural architectures (Zatorre, 2013) whose development undergoes critical periods (Penhune, 2011; Werker and Hensch, 2015) – specific time windows in early development, during which an organism’s neural functioning is open to be structured and shaped by the perception of external inputs, such as auditory texture. The present talk will bring evidence of the neural and cognitive mechanisms at play in music and language processing, focusing on speech and song perception and the discrimination of consonant intervals, such as perfect-fifth and octave intervals. Additionally, we will address the phenomenon of music-cultural perceptual narrowing, specifically looking at the perception of familiar and unfamiliar metrical structures (Hannon & Trehub, 2005).
‘Nadya wrote a letter (completely).’ (Urdu / Hindi)
(1) b.
rɑm bɑgh-ṭɑ-ke mer-e phel-l-o
Ram.Nom tiger-Cl-Acc hit-Gd throw-Past-3
‘Ram killed the tiger.’ (Bengali)
This was and is a rather startling claim that ran counter to much of thinking in the grammaticalizationliterature (e.g., Hopper and Traugott (1993), Bybee et al. (1994), Hook (1991, 2001)). However, there isa set of supporting evidence. For example, the modern Indo-Aryan morphological causative is not muchdifferent from how it was over 2000 years ago (Butt 2003, Jamison 1976, Speijer 1886) and Davison (2014)notes that the complex predicate permissive with ‘give’ also already appears to have existed in Old Indo-Aryan. Beyond Indo-Aryan, there is crosslinguistic evidence that light verbs indeed tend to be historicallystable (cf. Bowern 2008, Brinton and Akimoto 1999, Iglesias-R´abade 2001).
More recently, Slade (2013) and Ittz´es (2022) as well as Peter Hook (p.c.) have taken issue withButt&Lahiri’s claim as to the historical pertinacity of light verbs. In this talk, we go through these newerclaims and data in some detail and show that Butt&Lahiri’s claim as to the pertinacity of light verbs not onlyholds up, but is confirmed by the data adduced in both Slade (2013) and Ittz´es (2022).
Slade (2013) concentrates on examining evidence for grammaticalization from verbs that he assumes tobe light verbs. However, a close look at the data shows that Slade does not carefully distinguish betweenlight verbs, modals and auxiliaries (cf. Butt 2010) and that all of the examples adduced seem to either involvean auxiliary developing from a main verb (e.g., progressive rAh from ‘stay/remain’, cf. Bybee et al. 1994 forinstances of this well-established type of change) or modals (e.g., sAk ‘can/be able to’). We show that oncethis analytical confusion is sorted through, the data does not run counter to Butt&Lahiri’s claim.
Ittz´es (2022) looks at Sanskrit (and Vedic) N-V formations in the context of the grammaticalization ofthe perfect in Indo-Aryan. However, the modern Indo-Aryan perfect/perfective arose from the adjectivalpast participle in -ta and the picture of the distribution and properties painted by Ittz´es (2022) of the OldIndo-Aryan N-V combinations is very much like the structure and properties described and analyzed byMohanan (1994) for modern Hindi N-V complex predicates. Furthermore, there are three major light verbsinvolved: ‘do’, ‘be’, ‘become’, which each show constraints on permissible combinations and frequencyeffects. This is exactly what is found for Urdu/Hindi in a corpus study conducted by Ahmed and Butt(2011). Thus, rather than adducing evidence against Butt&Lahiri’s claim as to the pertinacity of light verbs,Ittz´es (2022) provides more evidence for Butt&Lahiri’s claim from the domain of N-V combinations.
Peter Hook points to data from Grierson (1928). This data is interesting, but turns out to be too sparseto decide the matter one way or another. In conclusion, we show that overall Butt&Lahiri’s central claimcontinues to hold up— there are no instances of auxiliaries that have developed from light verbs.
References
Ahmed, Tafseer and Butt, Miriam. 2011. Discovering Semantic Classes for Urdu N-V Complex Predicates. In Proceedingsof the Ninth International Conference on Computational Semantics, IWCS ’11, pages 305–309, Oxford,United Kingdom.
Bowern, Claire. 2008. The Diachrony of Complex Predicates. Diachronica 25(2), 161–185.
Brinton, Laurel J. and Akimoto, Minoji (eds.). 1999. Collocational and Idiomatic Aspects of Composite Predicates inthe History of English. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Butt, Miriam. 2003. The Morpheme That Wouldn’t Go Away, unpublished Ms., University of Konstanz.
Butt, Miriam. 2010. The Light Verb Jungle: Still Hacking Away. In M. Harvey M. Amberber and B. Baker (eds.),Complex Predicates in Cross-Linguistic Perspective, pages 48–78, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Butt, Miriam and Lahiri, Aditi. 2013. Diachronic Pertinacity of Light Verbs. Lingua 135, 7–29.
Bybee, Joan, Perkins, Revere and Pagliuca, William. 1994. The Evolution of Grammar: Tense, Aspect and Modalityin the Languages of the World. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.
Davison, Alice. 2014. Non-finite complements and modality in dee-naa ‘allow’ in Hindi-Urdu. Natural Language andLinguistic Theory 32, 137–164.
Grierson, George Abraham. 1928. Linguistic survey of India, volume 9. Calcutta: Office of the Superintendent ofGovernment Printing, India, compiled 1903–1928, 11 v. in 20 : maps (part fold.) ; 36 cm, The Indo-Aryan Family.Central Group. Specimens of the Pah¯ar¯ı Languages and Gujur¯ı.
Hook, Peter Edwin. 1991. The Emergence of Perfective Aspect in Indo-Aryan Languages. In Elizabeth Traugott andB. Heine (eds.), Approaches to Grammaticalization, pages 59–89, Amsterdam: Benjamins.
Hook, Peter Edwin. 2001. Where do Compound Verbs come from? (and where are they going?). In Peri Bhaskararaoand K.V. Subbarao (eds.), The Yearbook of South Asian Languages and Linguistics, pages 102–130, New Delhi:Sage Publications.
Hopper, Paul J. and Traugott, Elizabeth C. 1993. Grammaticalization. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Iglesias-R´abade, L. 2001. Composite predicates in Middle English with the verbs nimen and taken. Studia Neophilologica73, 143–163.
Ittz´es, M´at´e. 2022. Light verb, auxiliary, grammaticalization: The case of the Vedic periphrastic perfect. Die Sprache54, 95–129.
Jamison, Stephanie. 1976. Functional Ambiguity and Syntactic Change: The Sanskrit Accusative. In Papers from the Parasession on Diachronic Syntax, 12th Regional Meeting of the Chicago Linguistic Society, pages 126–135.
Mohanan, Tara. 1994. Argument Structure in Hindi. Stanford, California: CSLI Publications.Slade, Benjamin. 2013. The diachrony of light and auxiliary verbs in Indo-Aryan. Diachronica 30, 531–578.
Speijer, J. S. 1886. Sanskrit Syntax. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidas, republished 1973.